Gratis verzending vanaf €35,-
Unieke producten
Milieuvriendelijk, hoogste kwaliteit
Professioneel advies: 085 - 743 03 12

The timeless mind: A thought experiment

Reading | Ontology | 2022-07-31

Complex,Surreal,Painting.,Woman's,Face,With,Chess,Pattern.,Spiral,Of

Mind cannot be reduced to matter. Therefore, instead of looking for the origin of mind, we must understand reality in semiotic terms: as a universal set of signifiers and meanings. This is the argument put forward by Massimilano Sorrentino and Daniela Panighetti in this essay.

In our previous two essays (see here and here), we have shown that there is reason to believe that mind may be older than is currently thought. More specifically, we outlined a scenario in which life on Earth is the work of a conscious author engaged in a creative process. From a third person perspective, this author’s first-person experience would be perceived as the activity of the Earth’s atmospheric system, corresponding in this scenario to the author’s ‘brain.’ If this is indeed the case, we must push the appearance of mind back to at least four billion years ago; in other words, to the time when life is currently thought to have first appeared on Earth.

The issue we would like to explore now actually precedes the question of the origin of the mind. What we would now like to ask is whether it is possible for mind to have had an origin at all. Such a question is naturally too complex to be addressed in just a few lines, so we will broach a simplified version of it, tackling the problem from an epistemological perspective. We therefore suggest posing the following question: is it possible to construct a well-formulated theory illustrating the way in which mind originated from matter at a certain point in the past?

Irrespective of how far back in time we might push the appearance of mind, we believe that it is not possible to develop a well-formulated theory of its actual origin under materialism. The ultimate reason for the inability to do so stems from the fact that mental contents emanate directly from our experience; conversely, we are unable to have direct experience of the hypothetical ontological substance known as matter, other than as a mental concept. The mind therefore holds an epistemological primacy as compared to matter: we have greater certainty of the existence of mind than we do of matter. Any attempt to explain the origin of mind taking matter as the starting point exhibits a divergence between the ontological plane and the epistemological one.

To delve deeper into this point, let us focus on the correspondence between mental and physical brain states. When we perceive a circular shape within our field of vision, a precise neural pattern is activated in the visual cortex. If that pattern is activated in a somewhat artificial manner, we nevertheless perceive a circular shape, regardless of whether a circular object is before us or not. Materialist theories of consciousness not only fail to explain the appearance of perceptual experience, they also do not explain why any particular brain state should be identical to the experience of perceiving a circular shape. In other words, they do not tell us anything about the nature of this puzzling neural code of perceptions. Conversely, when we refer to the genetic code, for example, we are well aware of the biochemistry responsible for the correspondence between base triplets and amino acids; and even if we were not familiar with it, we would nevertheless be able to research it rigorously, according to the scientific method. Under materialism, it is not possible to understand, in principle, how a theory of the origin of mind might be developed.

We wish to underline that the problem does not lie in the fact that, at present, we do not have a plausible theory of consciousness under materialism. Rather, the problem is that it does not appear possible to even imagine how such a theory might be formulated. Even if we had an understanding—down to the minutest physical detail—of the way in which the brain, the atmospheric system and other possibly conscious systems function, we would still be none the wiser as to why a system with certain physical characteristics should be endowed with consciousness. Moreover, we would remain equally ignorant as to why certain brain activation patterns correspond to whatever mental patterns they correspond to. An obstacle of this nature is not found in any other area of science, which should be no surprise: what we are trying to explain here—i.e., subjectivity—was excluded from scientific enquiry in the very delineation of the scientific method itself. In the scientific method, the subjective perception of heat is replaced by the objective height of a column of mercury. Therefore, when tackling the problem of consciousness in a world conceptualized as material and objective, it becomes impossible to recover the subject—i.e., an individual who experiences the sensation of heat. The problem, therefore, is a failure to remember that the subject has been excluded from the ontology for purely epistemological reasons—i.e., so as to formulate the scientific method.

We should note that such problems would not arise if the ontological and epistemological planes were not split, as in idealism. Indeed, in any idealism, the mind is assumed to be the only ontological substance, without an origin. In such an ontology, matter—the non-mental substance—would be replaced by the substance that makes up our very mental contents. In such a conceptualization, the subject cannot be excluded from the ontological set. Instead, we need to introduce a universal subject at the root of reality; a subject whose mental contents would be the ultimate reality of what we define as the physical world. In this conceptualization, when each of us refers to themselves by using the term ‘I’, ultimately it is the universal subject that is referring to itself.

With the introduction of such a universal subject, the mind-matter problem needs to be re-formulated in idealist terms: what is the relationship between the mental contents of such a universal subject—the objects of the so-called physical world, including the brain—and the private mental contents that belong to each of us? Obviously, we cannot expect to provide an answer that is certain, nor can we expect to give the matter an exhaustive treatment; we simply want to show how, under idealism, the problems that emerge appear easier to tackle than the unintelligible mind-matter problem.

Let us imagine that we built a computing machine equipped with a particle detector. The machine has output actuators whose parameters—voltage, frequency, etc.—encode the values of the physical properties of the detected particle, such as momentum, mass, charge, and so on. Let us also imagine that we can wear this machine as a backpack, so that the output actuators come in contact with the skin on our back. The output parameters of the machine are now perceivable as electrical stimulation of the skin. Let us further imagine that we spend enough time training ourselves to use this machine. Since we have built it, we know how the outputs are encoded. As such, through its ongoing use, we find it progressively easier to build a mental image of an event, starting from the machine’s response to the event.

In using the machine—which can be regarded as an appendage of our body and brain—we experience two types of mental content, which in semiotics are called ‘signified’ and ‘signifier.’ The signified pertains to the plane of content, while the signifier pertains to the plane of expression. In linguistics, they are the plane of words, as sequences of letters, and the plane of meaning, to which the sequences point. The code is what establishes the relationship between the two planes. For example, the genetic code establishes the rules of correspondence between certain base triplets (signifiers) and a specific amino acid (signified). Within a language, syntax describes the rules by which signifiers can be combined into sentences, while semantics describes the meaning of that which is signified. In the case illustrated above, the signifiers will be constituted by the level of output voltages generated by the machine, which we are able to experience as electric discharges on our body. That which is signified will, in turn, be the physical characteristics of the measured particle, as encoded by precise machine output patterns. As we continue to practice using this ‘prosthesis,’ the focus of our attention will gradually shift from signifiers to meanings—i.e., from felt electric discharges to the cognition of particle characteristics—in the same way that, as we learn a language and are able to read it with increasing ease, our attention tends to gradually shift from letters and words to meanings.

Now let us compare this scenario with the one proposed in our previous essay: the atmospheric system impacted by cosmic rays. We are not responsible for the creation of the atmospheric system. Rather, it spontaneously appeared as a self-organizing system at thermodynamic disequilibrium. What happens in idealist terms is this: a subset of the mental contents that constitute reality—namely, the subset associated with the earth’s atmospheric system—is organized so as to detect stimuli associated with the remaining mental contents, thereby producing output patterns according to a code known to the universal subject. We must explain the relationship between the atmospheric system and the private mental contents of the Earth by regarding the latter as mental contents of the universal mind as well. Among the whole ensemble of mental contents of which the universe is made, some elements, such as the lightning discharge patterns discussed in our previous essay, are signifiers, while others are signified.

This rationale can be equally applied to the emergence of the first nervous system on Earth; and it is possible to provide the same interpretation when it comes to our own mental contents. Nature is constituted by the mental contents of the universal subject, and our mental contents are a subset of those. They are the ‘signifieds’ that correspond to signifiers constituted by our brain’s discharge patterns, which in turn are mental contents of the universal subject, just like everything else.

We certainly cannot claim to have explained the relationship between mental contents and brain states; our reason for outlining the foregoing embryonic interpretation of such a relationship was simply to point out that, under idealism, the mind-matter problem is more tractable than under materialism. In other words, while in materialism we are faced with an unintelligible problem—given that consciousness is irreducible to matter—in idealism we are faced with more tractable problems, such as the problem of multiple minds (i.e., given that nothing other than the universal mind exists, why do there appear to be multiple minds?). We believe that, unlike the problems of materialism, this problem could be ascribed to language limitations. More specifically, we suggest that perception is related to the existence of a code that introduces a distinction between what things are (as symbols or signifiers) and what they represent (the ‘signifieds’ or meanings).

There are thus reasons to believe that the most suitable ontology to avoid the mind-matter issue is some form of idealism, such as the one we proposed.

 

Bibliography

  1. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992
  2. Nagel and T. Nagel, Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist and NeoDarwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False. New York: OUP, 2012

Subhash MIND BEFORE MATTER scaled

Essentia Foundation communicates, in an accessible but rigorous manner, the latest results in science and philosophy that point to the mental nature of reality. We are committed to strict, academic-level curation of the material we publish.

Recently published

|

The end of physics as we know it?

Prof. Dr. Caslav Brukner, Prof. Dr. Renato Renner and Dr. Eric Cavalcanti just won the Paul Ehrenfest Best Paper Award for Quantum Foundations. Their different no-go theorems make us reconsider the fundamental nature of reality. Bell’s theorem in quantum mechanics already confronted us with the fact that locality and ‘physical realism,’ in the sense that particles have predetermined physical properties prior to measurement, cannot both be true. But in certain variations of the Wigner’s Friend thought experiment an additional metaphysical assumption is now also put in question: the absoluteness of facts. In different words: can we safely assume that a measurement outcome for one observer is a measurement for all observers?

|

The perils of smuggling metaphysics into science

The acquiescence of physicalism within the broader cultural milieu allows for the smuggling of assumptions into scientific inquiry, which are then, in a circular manner, considered to be validated by science itself. This disastrous interplay perpetuates a continued myopia in distinguishing between the ontological claims of physicalism and the assumptions of scientific inquiry, argues Adebambo Adedire.

From the archives

|

Why did Nietzsche break with Schopenhauer’s Idealism?

Once an enthusiastic Idealist in the tradition of Arthur Schopenhauer, the later Friedrich Nietzsche broke from Schopenhauer’s philosophy with a vengeance. Adebambo Adedire argues that this shift had more to do with Nietzsche’s later rejection of the metaphysical project itself, than with the particulars of Schopenhauer’s Idealism. For Nietzsche was to eventually consider the goal of understanding the nature of reality both impossible and inherently demeaning to the human condition. Yet, we ask, can a thinking human being ever stop wondering about what reality, and the self within it, ultimately are? Even if we, as primates, cannot arrive at the ultimate metaphysical answers, aren’t we correct in aspiring to overcome our own metaphysical mistakes and delusions?

|

Can we know the future? The science of precognition

Mainstream science still tends to dismiss extrasensory phenomena (ESP). However, these so-called ‘anomalous phenomena’ are key to understanding the nature of reality, claims Dr. Julia Mossbridge: “We are beginning to change the way we think as science enters the ‘maybe we got it all wrong’ phase.” In this interview, Natalia Vorontsova talks to Julia about her research in fields ranging from neuroscience and psychology to physiology and physics, tackling questions of free will, the nature of time, the mind-body problem, and key metaphysical implications.

|

Can there be a scientific form of spirituality?

Jonathan Dinsmore proposes applying the same cautious inferential reasoning used in the scientific method to developing metaphysical beliefs based on first-person experience. This may open the door to a form of spirituality that, although still grounded in personal insight and, therefore, not objective in a strict scientific sense, is nonetheless based on the form of disciplined thinking that has made science so successful.

Reading

Essays

|

Intelligence witnessed the Big Bang

Could it be a coincidence that two founding fathers of modern day computing, independently from each other, are both coming with theories of consciousness that are idealist in nature? Or does a deep understanding of what computation is—and what it is not—inevitably lead away from physicalist ideas on consciousness?

|

Enter Experimental Metaphysics

Essentia Foundation’s Hans Busstra visited Vienna to attend a conference on the foundations of quantum mechanics, and interview physicists on the metaphysical implications of quantum mechanics. In this essay, he argues that what is called ‘experimental metaphysics’ might be at the heart of future progress in physics, and that philosophy and physics are moving closer together.

|

Why did Nietzsche break with Schopenhauer’s Idealism?

Once an enthusiastic Idealist in the tradition of Arthur Schopenhauer, the later Friedrich Nietzsche broke from Schopenhauer’s philosophy with a vengeance. Adebambo Adedire argues that this shift had more to do with Nietzsche’s later rejection of the metaphysical project itself, than with the particulars of Schopenhauer’s Idealism. For Nietzsche was to eventually consider the goal of understanding the nature of reality both impossible and inherently demeaning to the human condition. Yet, we ask, can a thinking human being ever stop wondering about what reality, and the self within it, ultimately are? Even if we, as primates, cannot arrive at the ultimate metaphysical answers, aren’t we correct in aspiring to overcome our own metaphysical mistakes and delusions?

|

Can we know the future? The science of precognition

Mainstream science still tends to dismiss extrasensory phenomena (ESP). However, these so-called ‘anomalous phenomena’ are key to understanding the nature of reality, claims Dr. Julia Mossbridge: “We are beginning to change the way we think as science enters the ‘maybe we got it all wrong’ phase.” In this interview, Natalia Vorontsova talks to Julia about her research in fields ranging from neuroscience and psychology to physiology and physics, tackling questions of free will, the nature of time, the mind-body problem, and key metaphysical implications.

|

Can there be a scientific form of spirituality?

Jonathan Dinsmore proposes applying the same cautious inferential reasoning used in the scientific method to developing metaphysical beliefs based on first-person experience. This may open the door to a form of spirituality that, although still grounded in personal insight and, therefore, not objective in a strict scientific sense, is nonetheless based on the form of disciplined thinking that has made science so successful.

Seeing

Videos

|

Can we be both rational and spiritual? Prof. John Vervaeke on solutions to the meaning crisis

Hans Busstra sat down with John Vervaeke to discuss the meaning crisis, the Zombie myth we’re in, and how it all relates to what Vervaeke calls “rabbit hole metaphysics”: the conspiratorial, outlandish and often absurd ideas people start believing in, in search of meaning. A characteristic of rabbit hole types of metaphysics is that they have a ‘thick’ description of reality: a constellation of ungrounded assumptions build up to a ‘once you get this, there’s no way back’ narrative, which repeats itself in online echo-chambers.

|

Is reality made of language? The amazing connection between linguistic and physical structures

The structures of our language, which function as directly accessible carriers of meaning, reveal remarkable parallels to physical systems—particularly quantum systems—which can therefore be regarded as carriers of meaning as well. This profound interconnectedness of language, thought and reality challenge our conventional understanding of what is going on, argues Dr. Sachs. His insightful observations reveal surprising ways to make sense of the paradoxes of quantum mechanics along linguistic—and therefore thought-like—lines. Though involved, we highly recommend that you give this essay a careful read, as it is surely worth the effort.

|

Discussing quantum consciousness with world’s greatest minds: Penrose vs Faggin vs Kastrup

Two giants of science and technology—Nobel Laureate in physics, Sir Roger Penrose, and inventor of the microprocessor, Federico Faggin—meet to discuss their ideas on the relationship between Quantum Physics and consciousness, with the special participation of our own Bernardo Kastrup. While always respectful and congenial, the participants don’t shy away from disagreements. Their starting difference regards Quantum Theory itself: while Federico Faggin and Bernardo Kastrup allow its implications to inform their views, Sir Roger Penrose believes the theory itself to be at least incomplete and require further development. The discussion helps pin down and make explicit the fine points of the three gentlemen’s respective ideas regarding consciousness.

Let us build the future of our culture together

Essentia Foundation is a registered non-profit committed to making its content as accessible as possible and without advertisements. Therefore, we depend on contributions from people like you to continue to do our work. There are many ways to contribute.

Essentia Contribute scaled